Postulates and Proofs
5.1 Euclid's Postulates
In addition to the great practical value of Euclidean Geometry, the
ancient Greeks also found great esthetic value in the study of geometry.
Much as children assemble a few kinds blocks into many varied towers, mathematicians
assemble a few definitions and assumptions into many varied theorems. The
blocks are assembled with Hands, the postulates are assembled with Reason.
All of Euclidean Geometry (the thousands of theorems) were all put together
with just 5 different kinds of blocks. These are called "Euclid's
five postulates":
-
P-1 Every two points lie on exactly one line.
-
P-2 Any line segment with given endpoints may be continued in either
direction.
-
P-3 It is possible to construct a circle with any point as its center
and with a radius of any length. (This implies that there is neither
an upper nor lower limit to distance. In-other-words, any distance, no
mater how large can always be increased, and any distance, no mater how
small can always be divided.)
-
P-4 If two lines cross such that a pair of adjacent angles are congruent,
then each of these angles are also congruent to any other angle formed
in the same way.
-
P-5 (Parallel Postulate): Given a line L and a point not on L, there
is one and only one line L1 which contains the point, is in the same plane
as L, and is parallel to L.
Euclid's goal was for these postulates to be (1) few in number, and (2)
so obviously true that they could not possible be argued with. For
over 2000 years many mathamtitions believed that the fifth postulate (the
Parallel Postulate) was not needed. They believed that it could instead
be proved as a theorem of the first four postulates. There were numerous
attempts to do so. It was not until the nineteenth century that Lobachevski
(1793-1856), Bolyai (1777-1855) and Gauss (1802-1860) finally put an end
to this impossible search. Lobachevski developed theorems using Euclid's
first four postulates and the negation of the Parallel Postulate.
His expectation was to eventually develop two theorems which contradicted
each other. This would prove that negating the Parallel Postulate
is inconsistent with the first four postulates - thereby proving the Parallel
Postulate (and making it the Parallel Theorem). To his surprise, however,
he never obtained a contradiction. Instead, he developed a complete and
consistent geometry - the first non-Euclidean Geometry. This proved
that the Parallel Postulate could not be derived from the other four.
This was of great mathematical and philosophical interest. From the
time of the Greeks, it was believed that geometric theorems were such pure
and perfect Truth that they did not need to be scrutinized by observations
of the real world. Now, those statements are only true is some geometries.
The only reason to prefer one geometry over another is by comparison to
the real world. In spite of this philosophical and esthetic interest,
it was believed that non-Euclidean geometry was of no practical value.
Then, in the early 1900's, Einstein (1878-1955) developed The General Theory
of Relativity which made extensive use of a particular non-Euclidean Geometry
called Hyperbolic Geometry. This abstract, mathematical philosophical
was now in the realm of Science.
Hyperbolic Geometry is a Non-Euclidean Geometry based on the first four
of Euclid's postulates together with the following variation of the Euclidean
Parallel Postulate.
5.2 Hyperbolic Parallel Postulate:
Given a line L and a point not on L, there are at least two lines L1
and L2 which contain the point, are in the same plane as L
and are parallel to L.
5.3 SAS Postulate:
The SAS Postulate is a sixth postulate that is required in both Euclidean
and Hyperbolic Geometry.
The SAS postulate states that if two sides and the included angle of
one triangle are congruent to two sides and an included angle of a second
triangle, then the two triangles are congruent.
In the Elements, Euclid presents what he believes to be a proof for
SAS:[Health-56]
Given:
DABC and DDEF,
with sides AB @ DE, side AC @
DF, and Ð A @
Ð D.
Proof:
Move DABC such that point A coincides with
point D, and line AB coincides with DE.
Point B will coincide with E, because sides AB @
DE.
Also, line AC will coincide with DF, because ÐA
@ ÐD.
Point C will coincide with F, because sides AC @
DF.
Line BC will coincide with EF, because two lines cannot inclose a space.
Finally, side BC is congruent to side EF, because the lines and endpoints
of each coincide.
Therefore, ÐB @
ÐE, ÐC @
ÐF, and DABC
@ DDEF.
The flaw in the above argument is that it depends on the undefined term
"move". Let "move" (in both Euclidean and Hyperbolic
Geometry) be defined as a function that maps a set of points, P1, P2, P3,
... to P'1, P'2, P'3..., in such a way that for any two points Pn and Pm
of the original set, the distance from Pn to Pm equals the distance from
P'n to P'm. Then, for SAS to hold, it must be that for
any two lines L and L', it is always possible to "move" line L so that
it coincides with L'. This condition is commonly
called the SAS postulate, and it is the sixth postulate in both Euclidean
and Hyperbolic Geometry. [Moise-74]
5.4 Hyperbolic Geometry Proofs:
In addition to these postulates, both Euclidean and Hyperbolic geometry
require a number of common notions of reason such as "Things which are
equal to the same thing are also equal to one another" and "of any three
points on a line, exactly one is between the other two." All of these
common notions are exactly the same for both geometries. In fact,
the only difference between the complete axiomatic formation of Euclidean
Geometry and of Hyperbolic Geometry is the Parallel Postulate.
This is a powerful statement. It means that any proof in Euclidean
Geometry which does not use the Parallel Postulate is also a proof in Hyperbolic
Geometry!
Likewise, it means that Euclidean Geometry theorems that require the
Parallel Postulate will be false in Hyperbolic. A striking example
of this is the Euclidean Geometry theorem that the sum of the angles of
a triangle will always total 180º. Figure 5.4a may help you
recall the proof of this theorem - and see why it is false in Hyperbolic
Geometry.
Figure 5.4a: Proof for mÐA
+ mÐ B + mÐ
C = 180º
In Euclidean Geometry, for any DABC, there
exists a unique parallel to BC that passes through point A. Then,
Ð NAB @ Ð
ABC and Ð MAC @
Ð ACB since they are opposite interior angles
of a pair of parallel lines cut by a transversal. In Hyperbolic Geometry,
however, there are an infinite number of lines that are parallel to BC
and pass through point A, yet there does not exist any line such that both:
Ð NAB @Ð
ABC and Ð MAC @
Ð ACB.
NonEuclid Home
Next Topic - Area
Copyright©: Joel Castellanos, 1994-1997